Thucydides
These days, academics are accustomed
to explaining phenomenon in evolutionary terms: not just biological
evolution,
but social and political institutions as well are thought of in context
of a
gradual advance from the simple to the more advanced.
Again and again, you’ll see social scientists
and historians titling or subtitling their books the evolution of this
or that
or the other thing. Very often, this is
because adding the words “the evolution of…” makes it sound like what
you’re
doing is scientific, as scientific and rigorous as the kinds of things
the
biologists are doing. But we often end
up talking about “the evolution” of things that can’t possibly evolve,
and
biologists find some of our titles amusing and absurd.
Here at the NSU library, we’ve got the
evolution of Educational Doctrine, the Negro College, Shakespeare’s
comedy, the
English Novel, mathematical concepts, wage structure, a Chinese Novel,
early
Christianity, prohibition, psychotherapy, the ordinance of 1787, the
Constitution
of the United States, Terrorist Delinquency in Argentina, and (my
favorites)
the machine, Hungary, and Walt Whitman.
Machines can’t evolve. And Walt
Whitman by himself can’t evolve.
So why do we so constantly talk about
evolution of things that can’t evolve?
Well, there is a process of gradual change over time that, in
many
fields, is well worth looking at.
We can sometimes explain art, literature,
religion,
agricultural, economics, politics—everything—in terms of these gradual
changes
and improvements. And sometimes, this is
a good way to explain things (my lectures for example have “evolved”:
but just
imagine how bad they were to start with!).
But sometimes the gradual evolution explanation just won’t work:
even in
biology, the idea of gradual improvement is challenged by those who
believe in
catastrophism.
In the case of Thucydides, too, the
idea that the discipline of history came about as a result of gradual
evolution
just doesn’t work very well. Thucydides
history is enormously impressive, and one would think such a great work
would
have had to be proceeded by hundreds of simpler but inferior works. One would expect there to be centuries of
gradual improvements in history until at last one gets Thucydides. But that’s not the way it was.
We know of a few attempts at something sort
of like history before the time of Thucydides (those of Hellanicus and
Hecataeus, for instance), but these men were near contemporaries of
Thucydides,
and the fragments of their works that survive show that they weren’t
especially
impressive as historians. And prior to
this? Not much. Hecataeus
himself, commenting on the writers
before his time, noted that there wasn’t much in the way of solid
history. “The
Greeks tell many stories, and foolish ones at that.”
Well, in the late 5th
century BC, all of a sudden we get Herodotus—an impressive writer,
although he
often leaves much to be desired as an historian. And
then we get Thucydides, a man who writes
a history that has seldom been equaled and never, ever surpassed. One can explain later historians easily
enough: they built on the model of Thucydides (as did Xenophon and
Polybius) or
on the model of Herodotus. But
Thucydides comes out of nowhere, building on nothing: and creates for
us the
first scientific history. In addition,
Thucydides in some ways deserves credit also for being the father of
political
science as well.
Now I’ve said that Thucydides builds
on nothing. Perhaps this isn’t quite
true. He does have the epics of Homer as
a source of inspiration. He has the
tragic playwrights also—and, as I’ve said, it may be that the
world-view of
tragedy gets it right: tragedy is real historical pattern.
But Thucydides also has helping him the
community he leaves in. The Athenian way
of life, with its emphasis on conversation in the agora, and speeches
in the
ecclesia, provided a first class education in politics and political
thinking. No need to go to grad
school! Simply to be part of the
Athenian assembly meant that one would get a better education in
political
thinking and practice than one can get anywhere today.
Every issue, and I mean every issue, was
debated in the assembly. In addition to
all that, Thucydides has the advantage of having served in the war he
describes
himself—the kind of advantage Churchill has in writing his history of
WWII—and
that carries over into Churchill’s other histories.
What we have, then, in Thucydides, is
perhaps a logical enough extension of the kind of political debates
that took
place in Athens at its height.
Now when we were discussing Herodotus,
we started by trying to establish some criteria for a good history. In looking at Thucydides, it’s worth looking
first of all at how well Thucydides matches up to the same criteria by
which we
evaluated Herodotus.
Class
discussion focused on the strengths and weaknesses of
Thucydides, noting how well he matches up to our earlier discussion of
what the
characteristics that make for good history, e.g., a clear purpose,
interesting
content, clear sources, logical structure, and understanding of
cause/effect,
etc.).
Questions
in class/that you should ask yourself as you prepare this
material included the following:
1. Is
there a clear purpose here?
What is Thucydides purpose?
2. What
about Thucydides use of sources? Does he
use good sources? Does he make his sources
clear?
3. What
do you think of the technique of invented speeches?
Is this a legitimate technique for a
historian to use? (Cf., “The Reagans”
and the AIDS made-up comment).
THE PLAGUE:
2.
Leadership. What makes a
good leader? Examples?
What makes a man admirable in his eyes? What
characteristics does he dislike? (Cf.,
II:60, Pericles justification of his
policies. Note examples/contrasts in leadership styles, e.g.,
Diodotus and Cleon in
Mytilene debate:
THE MYTILENE DEBATE:
1. Did the people of Mytilene
have a right to revolt?
2. Did the Athenians have a
right to put down the revolt?
3. How should the Athenians
have treated Mytilene?
4. Is there any strength to
Cleon's argument (37-40)?
5. How does Cleon account for
the Athenian change of heart?
6. Is this a problem in
democracy?
7. What is Cleon's idea of
justice?
8. How does Diodotus defend
the orators?
9. How does he defend the
people of Mytilene?
10. How does the Spartan
treatment of Plataea compare to the Athenian treatment of Mytilene?
THE
MELIAN DEBATE:
1. Why is the debate not open
to the general public?
2. What is the Athenians
justification for requiring Melos to join their alliance?
3. Are the Melesian officials
right in refusing to submit to Athenian demands?
4. How do they hope to
withstand the Athenians?
5. Are the Athenians right in
saying their hopes are misplaced?
6. Should justice and fair
play be considerations in international relations?
FINAL
IMPRESSION
Why do
you suppose Thucydides didn't finish his history? Is
there any catharsis here?